logo

69 pages 2 hours read

C. S. Lewis

Mere Christianity

Nonfiction | Essay Collection | Adult | Published in 1952

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Book 1, Chapters 4-5Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Book 1: "Right and Wrong as a Clue to the Meaning of the Universe"

Book 1, Chapter 4 Summary: "What Lies Behind the Law"

Lewis begins by recapping the arguments of the previous chapters—namely, the difference between natural law as it applies to objects versus human behavior. Now, Lewis wishes to address what this tells us about the universe.

He points to two general approaches to this issue, the first of which is the materialist view. Those who hold this view believe in the Big Bang theory. Lewis emphasizes that this view involves a series of flukes where the odds were one chance in a thousand. The religious view, meanwhile, believes that “what is behind the universe is more like a mind than it is like anything else we know” (22). This mind is conscious and has purpose.

Lewis argues that science alone cannot prove which of these two theories is correct, since the religious view is attempting to answer a fundamentally different kind of question than those posed in science—not how something works but why there is anything to “work” in the first place, and whether that means something. To get around this impasse, Lewis notes that there is something that we understand through non-scientific means, and that is humanity. As human beings ourselves, we do not just observe humanity from the outside; in fact, any creature observing humanity from the outside would fail to understand key elements of human experience, including our sense of moral law, since this is not only about what we do but what we ought to do.

Lewis argues that this is precisely the kind of evidence that the religious view would expect and require, since this view is concerned not with the externally observable, material facts of the universe but rather with something non-material that is above or behind them: “The only way in which we could expect [a controlling power] to show itself would be inside ourselves as an influence or a command trying to get us to behave in a certain way. And that is just what we do find inside ourselves” (24).

At this point, Lewis notes that he only had time to mention the materialist view and religious view in his original radio broadcasts. There is also a third, “in between” view called life-force philosophy, creative evolution, or emergent evolution, which posits that life evolved due to the “striving” or “purposiveness” (26) of a life-force. Lewis queries whether this approach views the life-force as something with a mind. If so, then it is the same as the religious view. If not, then how can it strive or have purposes? Lewis sees it as flawed, though he realizes that it appeals to people because it offers “all the thrills of religion and none of the cost” (27).

Book 1, Chapter 5 Summary: "We Have Cause to Be Uneasy"

Lewis recognizes that some readers may feel that he has used philosophy as a front for his religious agenda and has set the clock back by turning to this subject. His response is threefold.

Firstly, he believes that humanity is on the wrong road and what might seem “backward” to some readers may be the direction that is needed for progress.

Secondly, he points out that he has not even focused on an idea of God; rather, he has argued that there is someone/something behind our moral law and that we can investigate the nature of this something for ourselves, both by thinking about the kind of universe we live in and (better yet) the nature of moral law. Most notably, Lewis suggests that the stringency of our moral sense implies that God is not “good” in the sense of being indulgent or soft, which is a disquieting idea.

Thirdly, Lewis has taken this roundabout approach because Christianity does not make sense without first acknowledging these moral points. The notions of repentance and forgiveness, for example, are key tenets of Christianity but are meaningless without an understanding of moral law. In fact, Lewis suggests that of all the religions, Christianity is best poised to explain and to resolve the tension he has outlined—namely, that humanity has a sense of morality that we constantly fail to live up to, and that whatever provided us with that sense of morality “must hate most of what we do” (31). Lewis therefore emphasizes that while Christianity itself can be a source of comfort in the long term, it “begins in […] dismay” (32). 

Book 1, Chapters 4-5 Analysis

In continuing to build his argument, Lewis observes that science and religion are concerned with two fundamentally different kinds of knowledge; science observes and describes how things happen (e.g. cause-and-effect relationships), whereas religion wonders what things mean and why things aren’t otherwise (e.g. why suffering exists). This is a fairly commonplace distinction, and in fact, Lewis himself clarifies that both the religious and the materialist approaches have always coexisted within human culture precisely because there are questions that no amount of scientific discovery can ever resolve: “Supposing science ever became complete so that it knew every single thing in the whole universe. Is it not plain that the questions, ‘Why is there a universe?’ ‘Why does it go on as it does’ ‘Has it any meaning?’ would remain just as they were?” (23).

From here, however, Lewis’s argument takes a more novel turn. One of the criticisms frequently levelled at religious belief in general is that it is a psychological defense mechanism that is, a way to avoid thinking about things like the meaningless of our existence and the inevitability of our mortality. In fact, Lewis himself concedes this point in his discussion of creative evolution:

When you are feeling fit and the sun is shining and you do not want to believe that the whole universe is a mere mechanical dance of atoms, it is nice to be able to think of this great mysterious Force rolling on through the centuries and carrying you on its crest (26-27).

However, Lewis contends that the alternative that is, the broadly “religious” view is at the very least equally unsettling, since it assumes that whenever we fail to heed our conscience, we’re disobeying whatever powerful entity gave us that conscience in the first place:

If the universe is not governed by an absolute goodness, then all our efforts are in the long run hopeless. But if it is, then we are making ourselves enemies to that goodness every day, and are not in the least likely to do any better tomorrow, and so our case is hopeless again (31).

Incidentally, this is what Lewis sees as appealing about the idea of a life-force it allows us to believe in a kind of purpose and meaning without demanding anything of us but he also argues that this idea doesn’t hold up under scrutiny, collapsing into either materialism on the one side or religion on the other.     

Ultimately, of course, Lewis will suggest that Christianity is best equipped both to explain this “terrible fix” (31) and to offer a way out of it. Even then, however, he will stress that Christianity is not an easy option, as it involves absolute commitment and overcoming a variety of hurdles. In other words, whether arguing in favor of religious belief in general or Christianity in particular, Lewis uses a very effective rhetorical strategy of adopting a clear-eyed and stoic tone common to materialist arguments. In doing so, he both strips those arguments of some of their power and suggests that it is his own position that is the truly courageous one: “All I am doing is to ask people to face the facts—to understand the questions which Christianity claims to answer. And they are very terrifying facts. I wish it was possible to say something more agreeable. But I must say what I think true” (32).

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text