logo

44 pages 1 hour read

Friedrich Engels

The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1884

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Prefaces-Chapter 1Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Preface to the First Edition Summary

Content Warning: This section of the guide includes discussions of sexuality, including incest, and references outdated and racist ideas and offensive language about the development of societies and cultures, replicated only in direct quotes of the source material.

Karl Marx had wanted to apply British anthropologist Lewis Henry Morgan’s theories of social evolution to his own economic theory but died before he could complete his research. Engels thus presents himself as trying in his own way to finish Marx’s task. Marxism is a materialist theory that understands the production of social institutions in light of economic forces, such as production and consumption. Societies are traditionally organized around ties of kinship, but as economic forces become more sophisticated, family structures are “completely dominated by the system of property” (36). Morgan’s work helps to elucidate this process, and Engels will rely on it consistently as he weaves it into an explicitly Marxist framework.

Preface to the Fourth Edition Summary

Seven years after the text was first printed, Engels has made some revisions, in part to fill gaps that he claims many critics would wish remained unfilled. The work has been published in many languages, helping to spread the concept of a history of the family, a relatively new subject of academic inquiry. The “patriarchal family” of the modern West is taken as the standard, essentially equivalent to the Biblical account of family, while traditions from other cultures are dismissed as curiosities. He cites Johann Bachofen’s analysis of early cultures as being polysexual, with lineage traced from the mother due to the certainty of maternal parentage, until certain religious developments prompted a shift to monogamy, and ultimately the domination of men. He looks at Aeschylus’s cycle of plays The Oresteia as representing a transfer in authority from mother to father, as the gods forgive Orestes for killing his mother, since she was guilty of killing his father. Engels asserts that while Bachofen has made a valuable contribution, he errs in overvaluing the role of religion. Nonetheless, his work helped to show that women once enjoyed a great deal more freedom, both sexually and socially, than under the current system of patriarchal monogamy.

Engels cites the Scottish social anthropologist John Ferguson McLennan as having introduced the field of the history of the family to an English language audience. McLennan’s work examines the customs of determining what makes a person eligible or ineligible for marriage within different cultures, and how certain practices such as bride-theft evolved from the relative paucity of female members within a tribe (often due to infanticide). Other scholars, including Morgan, challenge McLennan on the grounds that “consanguinity”—building families off existing bloodlines, often through group marriage—is more widely practiced than “exogamy”—acquiring wives from outsiders—as McLennan argues (45-47). Morgan also explains more clearly how patriarchy emerged historically from earlier matriarchy, aligning it with a fellow evolutionary theory like Marxism. If Morgan’s ideas are not being taken seriously, Engels blames this on a bias against American scholars and on fear of radical change: Admitting the possibility of a radically different family unit opens the door to Marxist notions of “a future transformation” of society itself. It is time for his ideas to have their proper hearing and application to contemporary social science.

Chapter 1 Summary: “Stages of Prehistoric Culture”

According to Morgan, humankind begins in a condition of so-called “savagery” in which humans are little more than slightly more sophisticated primates capable of living in tall trees to avoid predators. The development of fire, and the consequent ability to cook meat, enabled mass migrations across the globe, generating new sources of food and tools for its acquisition, but still requiring cannibalism for a consistent food source. Then, the development of the bow and arrow made true hunting possible, for both food and game, allowing human beings to have a more settled existence and develop other tools such as axes and canoes.

The next stage is “barbarism,” characterized mainly by the domestication of animals in Europe and the development of agriculture in the Americas. The pastoral life that developed in Europe, overseeing large herds of livestock on grasslands, prompted migrations in search of more favorable land. According to Morgan, with a heartier diet, Europeans developed larger brains than Indigenous people, who thrived almost entirely on vegetables, and as a result, the Europeans were first to pass into the “higher stage” of barbarism (55), marked by the development of iron ore. The wealth of technology that springs from iron marks the passage from barbarism to civilization, as people are inventing not only things but also culture and art.

Prefaces-Chapter 1 Analysis

The Origins of the Family can be seen as belonging to the first generation of Marxist theory after Marx, and as such its early chapters follow a pattern that would help set the standard for future generations of Marxist scholarship. In its opening words, it invokes the memory of Marx, who had died only the previous year, as an iconic figure whose legacy the book will help to solidify. Engels could lean on the legitimacy of Marx with ease, given their decades of collaboration on the core texts of the Marxist canon, but future Marxists would be no less eager to tie their work to the great man himself. Engels assumes that his readers are familiar with the fundamentals of the Marxist canon. He is interested in applying Marxist theory to the field of anthropology, particularly in regard to family, but he does not rehash the details, and in moments where his insights most closely align with his or Marx’s previous statements, he lets the comparison stand implicitly without drawing attention to it. This is therefore a text for the familiar, both supporters of Marxism looking for a new body of evidence outside the typical fields of economics and politics, as well as for opponents who seek refutations of Marxism in other fields of inquiry (in Engels’s view, because the Marxist view of economics is so self-evidently correct as to preclude a direct challenge).

As he and Marx do in The Communist Manifesto, which they wrote together, Engels turns to the literary canon to find evidence for his broadest claims. He cites Aeschylus’s tragedy The Oresteia as signaling The Shift from Matriarchy to Patriarchy: “the dramatic representation of the conflict between declining Mother Right and Father Right that arose and triumphed in the heroic age” (40). Aeschylus’s plays are thus significant insofar as they mark a major period in history, when the longstanding norm of Mother Right, or the respect accorded to the mother as the bearer of children and principal household laborer, was thwarted by the civilizing agents of Father Right, which assigns tyrannical authority based on the idea that women and children are naturally inferior to men. The totalizing theoretical framework of Marxism draws everything into its orbit: Everything worth studying can be submitted to Marxist analysis, and as Engels will make clear, the ascent of Father Right is the precondition for the rise of capitalism. Engels treats the field of anthropology, and Henry Lewis Morgan’s work in particular, as the raw material for his own theorizing about The Conflict Between the Family and the State. This project bears similarities with the practice of historical revisionism, as Engels sets out to correct narratives of history that, in his view, serve to naturalize the power of the ruling classes. McLennan’s dismissal of endogamous marriages among premodern peoples, for example, forms part of an “artificially constructed historical series” that presents exogamous and monogamous marriage as a natural state of being (49). For Marxists, historical narratives must always be examined according to the political and economic interests they serve.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text